MARXISM AND ECONOMIC DETERMINISM
Written c. 1978; for private circulation.
In what sense, if any, was Marx an economic determinist? That is, in what sense, if any, did Marx hold that non-economic factors in human life were determined, controlled, or influenced by such economic factors as methods of production, distribution and exchange? If we can answer that question, we can go on to ask what degree of truth or usefulness can be ascribed to Marx’s views on the matter – although in fact I intend to leave that mainly to discussion, so that I can concentrate on questions of theory.
Now it may be questioned straight away whether even to approach such questions is at all a suitable activity for a philosophy group. Surely questions about what are the important factors in human activity and history is a matter of historical and political judgement. You just have to sort out what influences what, and decide on degrees of importance from some standpoint or other. At best our questions could belong to political philosophy, hardly in the mainstream of philosophical enquiry. That certainly seemed to me to be the implication of the way in which Marxism was approached in the Greats course at Oxford in the late 40s. Yet it is the achievement of Marx and Marxism to make such a way of parcelling out things no longer self-evidently right. For Marx questioned the idea that philosophy or anything else can rise above the level of awareness appropriate to a particular socio-economic epoch: philosophy is thus seen as itself a part of the process of history, and any alleged separation from that process is a retreat from reality into a world of mere ideas. Hence the orientation of a journal like Radical Philosophy, where social, economic and political reality and the possibility of changing it is taken as the starting point of any worthwhile continuation of the long discussion that has constituted western philosophy.
Thus our questions can remain legitimately on the agenda, as long as we realise that their position is a little precarious: for a conclusion that the theory to be discussed (one that is quite central to Marxism) was of no value would suggest that after all the topic was, for us, ultra vires.
Marxism is itself best seen as a process, both within the writing life of Marx and Engels, and in the subsequent century of assessment, criticism and development. But within the process can be discerned a few central theses which interlock. It is this interlocking factor that makes it dangerous to consider only one thesis at a time – which is what we shall mainly be doing. Hence it is worthwhile to attempt the briefest of glances at the system as a whole. Hence my attempt at a definition:
Marxism is
a way of looking at history
that sees our changing methods of producing goods for consumption, and use, as crucial in setting limits to what is possible in human relationships and understanding of reality, and sees, in particular, the present highly industrialised method as initially requiring (a) production for profit, (b) a division between the exploiting and the exploited classes, (c) lack of self-expression (i.e. alienation) at work, and (d) mystification of the exploited by the exploiters (i.e. ideology), but as ultimately enabling the exploited to take control and to set up a classless society producing to meet needs;
hence it is also
a revolutionary project
in which the exploited can act together in seizing their opportunity
to free themselves throughout the world by (a) dismantling the capitalist state,
and (b) creating a genuine community where all can express themselves in the sharing
of resources. The first paragraph is a statement of the primacy of the economic
– the question we are to discuss. But its relationship to the possibility of change
is made clear in the clause beginning “but as ultimately...”. From this
follows its relevance to the revolutionary project, since it is claimed that the
time for revolution is or will be ripe when industrial production is advanced to
a stage where production for individual profit, and the consequent dichotomy of
the population into exploiters and exploited, becomes an obstacle – in Marx’s phrase,
becomes a “fetter” – to such production. Thus the thesis is a central element in
the whole, and is arguably the most central element of all – or indeed, as Marx
himself calls it, the guiding thread of my studies
.
Let us turn to the exegesis of our passage. As Martin Nicolaus has pointed out1, it is part of a broad overview of the internal conflicts of capitalism. It is part of a Preface to a book only a small portion of which was ever published. Nor did his later Magnum Opus Capital, Nicolaus argues, really cover the same breadth of subject matter. It was only in the Grundrisse of (1858) – a rough draft not published until 1939 – that this was attempted. Thus we now have to hand the writing with which Marx could offer to give body to the grand claims of this paragraph. In other words, although Marx was given to setting out vast programmes for study, we have here something which is not merely programmatic, but a summary, written in 1859 when Marx was 41, of his position as a result of the lucubrations of the previous year, and his earlier studies.
At the core of the passage is the statement of the primacy of social being over
individual consciousness. We can perhaps see this as foreshadowing the later Wittgenstein’s
preoccupation with different forms of activity, forms of life. But for Marx it was
of course a standing of Hegel on his head. It is not the consciousness of men which
determines their existence
(a summary of Hegel’s position on history as equal to
the history of ideas) but on the contrary, their social existence determines their
consciousness
2. This is such a concise
statement that we will later have to unpack it in terms of the various propositions
with which it is surrounded. But it is worth noting that the word used
bestimmt is usually rendered “determines”, whereas in the previous
sentence the corresponding word is bedingt, which can be translated
as “conditions”, although in fact given as “determines” in the translation before
us. Thus in the Lawrence and Wishart translation we read: The mode of production
of material life conditions the general process of social, political and intellectual
life
3. This seemingly weaker verb
is enough to remind us that Marx, although a materialist in the sense of denying
the primacy or sole reality of ideas, was not a mechanistic materialist. That is,
he did not hold that human behaviour could be explained simply in terms of the causality
exerted by physical objects on one another. As he wrote in the 3rd Thesis on Feuerbach
in 1845:
The materialist doctrine that men are products of circumstances and upbringing, and that therefore changed men are products of other circumstances and changed upbringing, forgets that it is men that change circumstances and that the educator himself needs educating4.
Admittedly, the relationship between people and circumstances could be seen in a merely mechanistic way, as though it depends upon from which you start your enquiry, as with the chicken and the egg. But Marx is clearly offering an argument, and must therefore be pointing to the agency of people over circumstances, an agency in some sense free. As an argument, it begs the question. But at least it stands as an assertion of the commonsense view that deciding to do something, to change circumstances, is not the same as, cannot be reduced to, being controlled by, being determined by, circumstances. As far as I know, Marx nowhere addresses the classic difficulties over freewill versus determinism. His implicit assertion of a position favouring freewill nevertheless deserves to be noted.
However the capacity for free choice does not exist in a vacuum. It exists always, for Marx, in a social and historical context. A decision to fly to New York in four hours is only possible since the invention and production of Concorde. Previously, one could only have wished to do so. Marx was concerned with these limitations or boundaries, within which free choice is possible, as we shall see as we now move on to some of the other propositions in our passage.
In the social production which men carry on they enter into definite relations
that are indispensible and independent of their will: these relations of production
correspond to a definite stage of development of the material powers (or forces,
in other translations) of production
. Marx is here making in respect of the production
of goods the same point that is often made regarding language: we take up the language
that is available, enter it “independently of our will”, and so too we enter into
relations of production; e.g. in feudal times people were born into a society where
lords owned and serfs toiled. Thus Marx is showing us two tiers: first the material
forces of production, and on top of that, as it were, the relations of production.
These relations are conceived of as including both the relations between people
engaged in production and property relations (See Michael Evans5.)
Immediately he adds a third tier, “legal and political superstructures” which rise
on the relations of production as if on a foundation. It is important to bear this
tripartite division in mind when a simpler formula, that of base and superstructure,
is employed – by Marxists, though not, I think, by Marx himself.
How are these three tiers related? Sometimes Marx uses the weak word “corresponds”,
but a stronger relationship is expressed by “conditions” and “determines”. Raymond
Williams6 points out that there is
a sharp difference between an external cause which totally predicts or prefigures,
indeed totally controls a subsequent activity
, and a notion of determination as
setting limits, exerting pressures
. As we saw in the 3rd Thesis on Feuerbach, Marx
adopted the second of these two positions in 1845, when speaking rather more loosely
in terms of “circumstances” and their influence on people. Does he still take the
same position in 1859? It would seem so. For writing later to J Bloch7
Engels explained: Marx and I are ourselves partly to blame for the fact that the
younger people sometimes lay more stress on the economic side than is due to it.
We had to emphasise the main principle vis-a-vis our adversaries, who denied it,
and we had not always the time, the place and the opportunity to give their due
to the other elements involved in the interaction
. Now if the “other elements”,
i.e. elements higher in the three tiers of the model, can also influence the lower
ones, the kind of “determination” spoken of must be of the limit-setting, pressure-exerting
kind, not the mechanistic. For although reciprocal causality makes sense in physical
terms, as when the air and the balloon around it “determine” one another’s shape,
Engels explains in another letter that “automatic”, mechanistic causality is out
of the question. Writing to W Borgius in 1894 he says: So it is not… that the economic
situation produces an automatic effect. No. Men make their history themselves, only
they do it in a given environment, which conditions it, and on the basis of actual
relations already existing, among which the economic relations, however much they
may be influenced by the other, the political and ideological relations, are still
ultimately the decisive ones
8.
Earlier in the former letter Engels states explicitly: According to the material
conception of history, the ultimate determining element in history is the
production and reproduction of real life. More than this neither Marx nor I have
ever asserted. Hence if somebody twists this into saying that the economic element
is the only determining one, he transforms that proposition into a meaningless,
abstract, senseless phrase. The economic situation is the basis, but the various
elements of the superstructure – political forms of the class struggle and its results,
to wit: constitutions established by the victorious class after a successful battle
etc., juridical forms, and even the reflexes of all these struggles in the brains
of the participants, political, juristic, philosophical theories, religious views
and their further development into systems of dogmas – also exercise their influence
upon the course of the historical struggles and in many cases preponderate in determining
their form. There is an interaction of all these elements in which, amid
all the endless host of accidents (that is, of things and events whose inner interconnection
is so remote or so impossible of proof that we can regard it as non-existent, as
negligible), the economic movement finally asserts itself as necessary. Otherwise
the application of the theory to any period of history would be easier than the
solution of a simple equation of the first degree
.
What does Engels mean by the ultimate determining element
and the
economic movement finally asserts itself
? Or what do modern writers mean when
they speak of the economic being determining “in the last analysis”? How does one
know that one is at the ultimate, final, last point of enquiry? Even if the answer
to this question is clear, we seem to be back at the position of strong or mechanistic
determination after all, if “the economic movement finally asserts itself as necessary”.
A more fruitful line of enquiry will take us back to look in greater detail at
what is meant by the economic base itself, the material forces of production, of
“forces of material production”, equally a translation of the German phrase. (See
Nicolaus.) At first sight it seems that Marx is referring literally to material
objects such as spades, lathes and engines. Thus he writes in The Poverty of Philosophy
in 1847 (cited by McLellan): the hand mill will give you a society with the feudal
lord, the steam mill a society with the industrial capitalist
. But these tools
and machines need people to work them. As inert objects they are not productive
at all; in Marx’s terms they represent “frozen labour”, and so need living labour
to become productive. Hence the material forces of production must include the human
productive element as well. This is not merely a semantic point. For if the material
forces of production are physical objects and nothing more, then can exert only
physical, mechanistic, causality, if any, and Marx would after all be a mechanistic
materialist.
Thus the lowest tier, the economic, must be considered as a complex of productive
practices, such that a given set of practices requires an appropriate set
of social relations – by saying “an appropriate set” rather than “the appropriate
set” allows us to retain the limit-setting sense of economic determination. This
point about practices is well made by M Nicolaus (op. cit. p 324), who then goes
on to give a convincing example, from Marx’s own theory, of the downward influence
of the social relations upon the material forces of production: The forces of production
are themselves a social and historical product, and the productive process is a
social process for Marx. It is necessary to emphasise this point in order to make
clear that the important role which Marx assigns to the development of the material
production forces under capitalism does not make Marx a technological determinist.
Quite the opposite is the case; it is not technology which compels the capitalist
to accumulate, but the necessity to accumulate which compels him to develop the
powers of technology
.
Roy Bhaskar goes further, pointing out that ideas, usually assigned to the third,
highest, tier, must be involved also in the productive processes of the first, lowest,
one. He writes: all activity, including purely economic activity, necessarily has
an ideational component or aspect
. However, he continues a little later: Thus
the crude distinction economic base/ideological superstructure must be rejected,
and replaced instead by a conception of different ideologies associated
with different practices
. Now if this leaves us merely with an association
of ideologies and practices, as it seems to do, Bhaskar has left Marxism behind
him in any kind of primacy for the economic.
Is there then after all no stable position to hold between mechanistic determination on the one hand and Bhaskarian associationism on the other? I want to suggest that there is, on two sets of grounds. The first concerns the obvious fact that material, what Aristotle called “vegetative” life is the necessary basis on which individual intellectual life subsists. As I have argued this point in an earlier paper to this group9 I will only mention briefly that the argument turned on the fact that we are bodily beings with physical needs and expressive needs, neither of which can be adequately met by a system of production for profit rather than for use, i.e. commodity production. That form of production sets limits to what is possible, excluding the full satisfaction of both physical and expressive needs. It will be noticed that this attempt to hold a central position between mechanism and associationism depends on the factors we are ascribing to the process of determination i.e. on empirical factors, not on a formal distinction. But I suggest that it goes far enough by showing that the concept of a stable intermediate position is not an empty one.
The second ground is again empirical, and would lead us on to a consideration of the whole range of historical examples worked out by Marx. But if we keep to the broadest of perspectives it would seem to be obvious that a simple hunting economy did not permit the development of the kind of competitive, or in Marx’s terms “antagonistic”, society we take for granted today, simply because there could be no accumulated surplus to be individually appropriated (or plundered, or stolen). Again, given a machine-based culture and a capitalist mode of production the invention of a more efficient machine renders it impossible for an employer to keep to his old machines and remain competitive. But, as we have seen Nicolaus point out, the pressure to develop new machines (if capitalist A does not, he fears that capitalist B will) is a case of the social relation, competition between firms, influencing in its turn the material base.
Summing up, I have tried to show that Marx’s theory of economic determination is not mechanistic, but holds that the productive forces, which include the human element of the direct producers, condition, i.e. set limits to the possible development of, the social relationships of a given period, which in turn condition, in the same sense, the broad ways of thinking about and understanding the world generally prevalent at the same period. I have also offered, by way of illustration, a few empirical arguments for the truth of the theory.
1 Martin Nicolaus, The Unknown
Marx, in Ideology and Social Science, ed. R Blackburn, Fontana/Collins,
London 1972.
2 German Ideology, cited
in D McLellan, The Thought of Karl Marx, p 128.
3 in The Economics of Marx,
selected readings ed. M C Howard and J E King, Penguin, 1976.
4 Marx-Engels, Selected Works,
Lawrence and Wishart, London 1968, p 28.
5 Michael Evans, Karl Marx,
Allen & Unwin, London, 1975 p 63.
6 Raymond Williams, Base and
Superstructure in Marxist Cultural Theory, in Schooling and Capitalism,
ed. R Dale and others, Routledge, London 1976.
7 Marx-Engels Sel. Works, p 692.
8 ibid. p 705.
9
Alienation and Bodies, p 10